Docsity
Docsity

Prepare for your exams
Prepare for your exams

Study with the several resources on Docsity


Earn points to download
Earn points to download

Earn points by helping other students or get them with a premium plan


Guidelines and tips
Guidelines and tips

Malebranche and Occasionalism - Lecture Notes | PHIL 104, Study notes of Philosophy of Science

Material Type: Notes; Class: The Rationalists; Subject: Philosophy; University: University of California - San Diego; Term: Unknown 1989;

Typology: Study notes

2009/2010

Uploaded on 03/28/2010

koofers-user-rza
koofers-user-rza 🇺🇸

1

(1)

10 documents

1 / 3

Toggle sidebar

This page cannot be seen from the preview

Don't miss anything!

bg1
Philosophy 104 Prof. Don Rutherford
Malebranche and Occasionalism
1. The doctrine of occasionalism is the backbone of Malebranche’s philosophy.
Roughly, the doctrine asserts that God is the only real cause of any change in the world.
As against “the errors of the ancient philosophers,” Malebranche writes, he will establish
“that there is only one true cause because there is only one true God; that the nature and
power of each thing is nothing but the will of God; that all natural causes are not true
causes but only occasional causes…” (Philosophical Selections, 94). To call something
an “occasional causes” is to deny that it does anything to bring about a change in
something else; rather, the modifications of finite things (bodies, minds) are only the
occasions for God acting in the world.
2. The underlying motivation for this doctrine is, like so much else in Malebranche’s
philosophy, theological. This is apparent in the Search after Truth, VI.2.iii, a famous
chapter entitled “The most dangerous error of the philosophy of the ancients.” There
Malebranche argues that the idea of cause, or of power to act, represents something
divine. Therefore, any philosophy that assigns causal powers, forces, or substantial forms
to finite things is effectively a form of idolatry.
One of Malebranche’s most interesting arguments on behalf of this point is that we are
naturally prompted to love and fear “true powers--beings that can act upon us, punish us
with pain, or reward us with pleasure” (92). If we further assume that pain is an evil and
pleasure a good, then “reason seems to some degree to justify a religion similar to that of
the pagans, and to approve the universal disorder of morals” (93). We will end up
worshipping natural things (even leeks and onions!) as divinities, rather than God.
3. Malebranche also supports occasionalism with more properly philosophical
arguments. The most important of these rests on what we may call the True Cause
Principle (TCP):
“A true cause as I understand it is one such that the mind perceives a necessary
connection between it and its effects” (Philosophical Selections, 96)
TCP has some intuitive plausibility. It is commonly assumed that for a genuine causal
relation, a coincidence or mere correlation is insufficient. It is not enough simply for an
effect to follow a cause in a regular manner. In addition, the cause must somehow act to
bring it about that the effect occurs. Furthermore, causal connections should support
counterfactual statements of the form: if the cause had occurred, the effect would have
occurred, other things being equal (ceteris paribus). The ‘ceteribus paribus’ clause
responds to the fact that what we pick out as a cause (e.g. a lit match) is usually not a
total cause—other ancillary conditions (sufficient oxygen, absence of sprinklers, etc.)
have to be realized in order for the effect to be produced.
pf3

Partial preview of the text

Download Malebranche and Occasionalism - Lecture Notes | PHIL 104 and more Study notes Philosophy of Science in PDF only on Docsity!

Philosophy 104 Prof. Don Rutherford Malebranche and Occasionalism

  1. The doctrine of occasionalism is the backbone of Malebranche’s philosophy. Roughly, the doctrine asserts that God is the only real cause of any change in the world. As against “the errors of the ancient philosophers,” Malebranche writes, he will establish “that there is only one true cause because there is only one true God; that the nature and power of each thing is nothing but the will of God; that all natural causes are not true causes but only occasional causes…” ( Philosophical Selections , 94). To call something an “occasional causes” is to deny that it does anything to bring about a change in something else; rather, the modifications of finite things (bodies, minds) are only the occasions for God acting in the world.
  2. The underlying motivation for this doctrine is, like so much else in Malebranche’s philosophy, theological. This is apparent in the Search after Truth , VI.2.iii, a famous chapter entitled “The most dangerous error of the philosophy of the ancients.” There Malebranche argues that the idea of cause, or of power to act, represents something divine. Therefore, any philosophy that assigns causal powers, forces, or substantial forms to finite things is effectively a form of idolatry. One of Malebranche’s most interesting arguments on behalf of this point is that we are naturally prompted to love and fear “true powers--beings that can act upon us, punish us with pain, or reward us with pleasure” (92). If we further assume that pain is an evil and pleasure a good, then “reason seems to some degree to justify a religion similar to that of the pagans, and to approve the universal disorder of morals” (93). We will end up worshipping natural things (even leeks and onions!) as divinities, rather than God.
  3. Malebranche also supports occasionalism with more properly philosophical arguments. The most important of these rests on what we may call the True Cause Principle (TCP) : “A true cause as I understand it is one such that the mind perceives a necessary connection between it and its effects” ( Philosophical Selections , 96) TCP has some intuitive plausibility. It is commonly assumed that for a genuine causal relation, a coincidence or mere correlation is insufficient. It is not enough simply for an effect to follow a cause in a regular manner. In addition, the cause must somehow act to bring it about that the effect occurs. Furthermore, causal connections should support counterfactual statements of the form: if the cause had occurred, the effect would have occurred, other things being equal ( ceteris paribus ). The ‘ ceteribus paribus ’ clause responds to the fact that what we pick out as a cause (e.g. a lit match) is usually not a total cause—other ancillary conditions (sufficient oxygen, absence of sprinklers, etc.) have to be realized in order for the effect to be produced.

Accepting this we might think that the conjunction of the cause and the ancillary conditions necessitates the effect. That is, [1] C & A => E. But the necessity operative here can’t be a logical necessity, for it is consistent with the occurrence of C and A that E not occur (given our experience of nature we wouldn’t expect this to happen, but it could happen). We get the necessity we want—a necessity meeting the condition of TCP —if we add the requirement that certain laws of nature (L) govern the operation of causes. That is, [2] Nec ((C & A) & L => E) This schema is an instance of the thesis of determinism, which asserts that given any event (C & A) and the laws of nature, some other event (E) is necessitated. The deep question is how to conceive of these laws of nature. How do they introduce a necessity in [2] that wasn’t present in [1]? Malebranche answers this by asserting that the laws of nature are “efficacious divine volitions.” Thus, they are the true cause of E. (C & A) is only an occasional cause.

  1. There is an important historical connection between Malebranche’s position and that of David Hume. Hume agreed with Malebranche that the relation of causation involves the idea of necessary connection, but he argued that the mind never directly perceives a necessary connection between cause and effect. From this he concluded, that for all we know, there are no real necessary connections among things in the world; rather it is the mind that impose the idea of necessity on things, when it is has been conditioned by experience to connect them. Hume’s claim is primarily an epistemological one, and he does not use it to support a theological position in the way Malebranche does. (So we might think of Hume as Malebranche without God.)
  2. In applying TCP , Malebranche’s concerns are primarily metaphysical. Reason is the judge of which things qualify as causes. Here Malebranche argues both that God satisfies TCP (Argument 1) and hence is a true cause and that only God can be conceived as a true cause (Arguments 2-4). Argument 1 God satisfies the condition of being a true cause, because the idea of an omnipotent being supports the claim that, necessarily, if God wills x (cause), x must follow (effect). Argument 2 (We perceive no causal power in finite things) (i) No such power is contained in the essence of matter (extension). (ii) The paradigm case of a cause is the will, but not the human will: we are aware of no power within ourselves of producing any changes we please (neither changes in our