Docsity
Docsity

Prepare for your exams
Prepare for your exams

Study with the several resources on Docsity


Earn points to download
Earn points to download

Earn points by helping other students or get them with a premium plan


Guidelines and tips
Guidelines and tips

Jurisprudence: Origin, Theories, and Key Figures, Summaries of Law

An introduction to jurisprudence, exploring its history and key theories. Topics include the strong natural law thesis, legal positivism, and the pure theory of law. Notable figures such as austin, hart, kelsen, and their contributions to jurisprudential thought are discussed.

Typology: Summaries

2018/2019

Uploaded on 03/23/2019

vinay-dabas
vinay-dabas 🇮🇳

4

(1)

6 documents

1 / 4

Toggle sidebar

This page cannot be seen from the preview

Don't miss anything!

bg1
Jurisprudence- its Origin &
Theories
INTRODUCTION
HISTORY OF JURISPRUDENCE
Ghrtgjnr2jm2rq2rqwThe Strong Natural Law Thesis holds that if a human
law fails to be backed up by decisive reasons, then it is not properly called
a “law” at all. This is captureing of the morality enacted as law, not the
laws themselves. The passage here is silent as to that
question.8e67i46cfhlcbo03asdv
wThe most important questions of analytic jurisprudence are: “What are
laws?”; “What is thelaw?”; “What is the relationship between law and
power/sociology?”; and “What is the relationship between law and
morality?” Legal positivism is the dominant theory, although there are a
growing number of critics who oer their owdfbhfgustin was the rst chair
of law at the new University of London from 1829. Austin’s utilitarian
answer to “what is law?” was that law is “commands, backed by the threat
of sanctions, from a sovereign, to whom people have a habit of
obedience”. Contemporary legal positivists have long abandoned this
view, , H. L. A. Hart particularly.
Hans Kelsenethq
Hans Kelsen is considered one of the prominent jurists of the 20th century
and has been highly inuential in Europe and Latin America, although less
so in common-law countries. His Pure Theory of Law aims to describe the
law as binding norms while at the same time refusing, itself, to evaluate
those norms. That is, ‘legal science’ is to be separated from ‘legal politics’.
Central to the Pure Theory of Law is the notion of a ‘basic norm
(Grundnorm)’—a hypothetical norm, presupposed by the jurist, from which
in a hierarchy all ‘lower’ norms in a legal system, beginning with
constitutional law, are understood to derive their authority or
‘bindingness’. In this way, Kelsen contends, the bindingness of legal
norms, their specically ‘legal’ character, can be understood without
tracing it ultimately to some suprahuman source such as God, personied
Nature or—of great importance in his time—a personied State or Nation.
1. L. A. Hart
In the Anglophone world, the pivotal writer was H. L. A. Hart, who argued
that the law should be understood as a system of social rules. Hart
rejected Kelsen’s views that sanctions were essential to law and that a
pf3
pf4

Partial preview of the text

Download Jurisprudence: Origin, Theories, and Key Figures and more Summaries Law in PDF only on Docsity!

Jurisprudence- its Origin &

Theories

INTRODUCTION

HISTORY OF JURISPRUDENCE

Ghrtgjnr2jm2rq2rqwThe Strong Natural Law Thesis holds that if a human law fails to be backed up by decisive reasons, then it is not properly called a “law” at all. This is captureing of the morality enacted as law, not the laws themselves. The passage here is silent as to that question.8e67i46cfhlcbo03asdv

wThe most important questions of analytic jurisprudence are: “What are laws?”; “What is thelaw?”; “What is the relationship between law and power/sociology?”; and “What is the relationship between law and morality?” Legal positivism is the dominant theory, although there are a growing number of critics who offer their owdfbhfgustin was the first chair of law at the new University of London from 1829. Austin’s utilitarian answer to “what is law?” was that law is “commands, backed by the threat of sanctions, from a sovereign, to whom people have a habit of obedience”. Contemporary legal positivists have long abandoned this view, , H. L. A. Hart particularly.

Hans Kelsenethq

Hans Kelsen is considered one of the prominent jurists of the 20th century and has been highly influential in Europe and Latin America, although less so in common-law countries. His Pure Theory of Law aims to describe the law as binding norms while at the same time refusing, itself, to evaluate those norms. That is, ‘legal science’ is to be separated from ‘legal politics’. Central to the Pure Theory of Law is the notion of a ‘basic norm (Grundnorm)’—a hypothetical norm, presupposed by the jurist, from which in a hierarchy all ‘lower’ norms in a legal system, beginning with constitutional law, are understood to derive their authority or ‘bindingness’. In this way, Kelsen contends, the bindingness of legal norms, their specifically ‘legal’ character, can be understood without tracing it ultimately to some suprahuman source such as God, personified Nature or—of great importance in his time—a personified State or Nation.

1. L. A. Hart

In the Anglophone world, the pivotal writer was H. L. A. Hart, who argued that the law should be understood as a system of social rules. Hart rejected Kelsen’s views that sanctions were essential to law and that a

normative social phenomenon, like law, can not be grounded in non- normative social facts. Hart revived analytical jurisprudence as an important theoretical debate in the twentieth century through his book The Concept of Law.[5] As the professor of jurisprudence at Oxford University, Hart argued that law is a ‘system of rules’.

Rules, said Hart, is divided into primary rules (rules of conduct) and secondary rules (rules addressed to officials to administer primary rules). Secondary rules are divided into rules of adjudication (to resolve legal disputes), rules of change (allowing laws to be varied) and the rule of recognition (allowing laws to be identified as valid). The “rule of recognition” is a customary practice of the officials (especially barristers and judges) that identifies certain acts and decisions as sources of law. A pivotal book on Hart was written by wnasdasNeil MacCormick in 1981 (second edition due in 2007), which further refined and offered some important criticisms that led MacCormick to develop his own theory (the best example of which is his recently published Institutions of Law, 2007). Other important critiques have included that of Ronald Dworkin, John Finnis, and Joseph Raz.

In recent years, debates about the nature of law have become increasingly fine-grained. One important debate is within legal positivism. One school is sometimes called exclusive legal positivism, and it is associated with the view that the legal validity of a norm can never depend on its moral correctness. A second school is labeled inclusive legal positivism, a major proponent of which is Wil Waluchow, and it is associated with the view that moral considerations may determine the legal validity of a norm, but that it is not necessary that this is the case

NORMATIVE JURISPRUDENCE

In addition to the question, “What is law?”, legal philosophy is also concerned with normative, or “evaluative” theories of law. What is the goal or purpose of the law? What moral or political theories provide a foundation for the law? What is the proper function of law? What sorts of acts should be subject to punishment, and what sorts of punishment should be permitted? What is justice? What rights do we have? Is there a duty to obey the law? What value has the rule of law? Some of the different schools and leading thinkers are as follows.

Virtue jurisprudence

Aretaic moral theories such as contemporary virtue ethics emphasize the role of a character in morality. Virtue jurisprudence is the view that the laws should promote the development of virtuous characters by citizens.

References:

[1] Kare college of law

[2] Cambridge dictionary of philosphy

[3] Cambridge dictionary of philosphy

[4]Modern law review

[5] Oxford English dictionary

[6] Shellen “Aristotle on natural law”

[7] Cambridge dictionary